Hi, Jack!
My understanding is that the quotations are a response that a person made to a John-Loftus-inspired argument. Little work is required here.
In order for a collection of sentences to exist as an argument, each sentence in that collection must be a reasonably unambiguous, declarative sentence. “Unambiguous” means that the sentence clearly expresses exactly one statement. It is unclear why there is no “a” prior to the term “God-like entity”, and it is unclear what the term “God-like entity” is suppose to capture. (Consider how the number six is immaterial and exists outside of space and time. Those seem like God-like characteristics. Superman is marvelously powerful. That seems God-like. A pet cat may give you a sense of purpose and provide unconditional love. That’s God-like.) Due to this, there is no argument for the contention.
The importance of dispelling ambiguity is observed in practice, Jack, by noticing that secularism does not state or imply that there is no God-like entity, depending on how you interpret what is takes to be God-like. For instance, a being who gives you purpose and shows you unconditional love may be interpreted as being “God-like entity” and is compatible with secularism. Moreover, science and reason do not favor “God-like entity”, depending on how you interpret such a term. Scientific evidence doesn’t favor a perfectly moral entity, for instance, if that is part of the interpretation of God-likeness. As for reason, reason can favor contradictory interpretations of what counts as God-likeness (Aristotle and Aquinas both had reasons to believe in an entity that they believe is God-like, though both of their entities cannot exist at the same time and in the same sense, and both of their reasonings cannot be sound at the same time and in the same sense.) Thus, non-ambiguous sentences are required in order for an argument to exist and must precede the identification (telling whether a collection of sentences is an argument or not), analysis (recognizing the parts of an argument and how they connect to each other) and evaluation (telling whether an argument is good or bad) of an argument.
The ambiguity is useful in persuading listeners, since if the person intends for his contention to refer to God—and for whatever reason he is just shy about being so frank—then although this creates an unambiguous sentence, what too becomes plain to the eye is that the main argument which would appear for that contention out of the quotations that you have provided would be fallacious. The argument would be fallacious because from the fact that science and reason show that materialism is false, it would not follow that science and reason favor that God exists. For all that this shows, science and reason favor neither materialism nor the existence of God. Also, from the fact that science and reason show that objective monistic idealism is true, it would not follow that science and reason favor the existence of God. For all that this shows, science and reason favor that the one mind pervading all of reality is finite, or even hardly different than a human mind.
In sum, the contention is too ambiguous. Argumentation, and the logical study of an argument, such as testing it for fallacies, requires reasonably unambiguous, declarative sentences. If the person intends to refer to God, then the ambiguity was convenient, seeing how the main argument would commit the fallacy of non sequitur in two places: science and reason may favor neither materialism nor that God exists, and may favor both objective monistic idealism and a finite mind, for all that the person has shown.
Thank you, Jack.
From, Kaiden